Expected Utility Theory: When It Works, and Where It Fails

This article is an excerpt from the Shortform summary of "Thinking, Fast and Slow" by Daniel Kahneman. Shortform has the world's best summaries of books you should be reading.

Like this article? Sign up for a free trial here .

What is expected utility theory? How is it used to predict human behavior? And what are its flaws?

Expected utility theory is a theory of how people make choices and take risks when they don’t know the outcome. Traditional expected utility theory asserts that people are rational agents that calculate the utility of each situation and make the optimum choice each time. 

We’ll look at how expected utility theory for decision making works and cover some of its flaws.

Expected Utility Theory

How do people make decisions in the face of uncertainty? There’s a rich history spanning centuries of scientists and economists studying this question. Each major development in decision theory revealed exceptions that showed the theory’s weaknesses, then led to new, more nuanced theories.

Expected utility theory says that you’re a rational being who makes the optimum choice with the right information.

If you preferred apples to bananas, would you rather have a 10% chance of winning an apple, or 10% chance of winning a banana? Clearly you’d prefer the former.

Similarly, when taking bets, expected utility theory assumes that people calculate the expected value and choose the best option.

This is a simple, elegant theory that by and large works and is still taught in intro economics. But it failed to explain the phenomenon of risk aversion, where in some situations a lower-expected-value choice was preferred.

The Problem with Expected Utility Theory

Consider: Would you rather have an 80% chance of gaining $100 and a 20% chance to win $10, or a certain gain of $80? 

The expected value of the former is greater (at $82) but most people choose the latter. This makes no sense in classic utility theory—you should be willing to take a positive expected value gamble every time.

Risk Aversion and Bernoulli’s Expected Utility Theory

To address this, in the 1700s, Bernoulli argued that 1) people dislike risk, and that 2) people evaluate gambles not based on dollar outcomes, but on their psychological values of outcomes, or their utilities.

Bernoulli then argued that utility and wealth had a logarithmic relationship. The difference in happiness between someone with $1,000 and someone with $100 was the same as $100 vs $10. On a linear scale, money has diminishing marginal utility.

This concept of logarithmic utility neatly explained a number of phenomena:

Expected Utility Theory: When It Works, and Where It Fails

———End of Preview———

Like what you just read? Read the rest of the world's best summary of "Thinking, Fast and Slow" at Shortform . Learn the book's critical concepts in 20 minutes or less .

Here's what you'll find in our full Thinking, Fast and Slow summary :

  • Why we get easily fooled when we're stressed and preoccupied
  • Why we tend to overestimate the likelihood of good things happening (like the lottery)
  • How to protect yourself from making bad decisions and from scam artists

Amanda Penn

Amanda Penn is a writer and reading specialist. She’s published dozens of articles and book reviews spanning a wide range of topics, including health, relationships, psychology, science, and much more. Amanda was a Fulbright Scholar and has taught in schools in the US and South Africa. Amanda received her Master's Degree in Education from the University of Pennsylvania.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *